Is there a secular body? Or, in somewhat different terms, is there a particular configuration of the human sensorium—of sensibilities, affects, embodied dispositions—specific to secular subjects, and thus constitutive of what we mean by “secular society”? What intrigues me about this question is that, despite its apparent simplicity, the path toward an answer seems not at all clear. For example, are the scholarly sensibilities and the modes of affective attunement that find expression here elements of a secular habitus? What would be indicated by calling such expressive habits “secular”?
Clearly, they have been learned in a secular institution (i.e., a secular university). Would we say, therefore, that I am displaying the embodied aptitudes and habits of a secular person, and that a study of the educational techniques employed at the university would tells us how secular subjects are formed? If that were the case, then why, despite the plethora of studies on the education system in the U.S., do we not feel quite comfortable when asked to describe the embodied aptitudes of a secular subject? I should clarify before I go further that the notion of “secular” I employ here does not stand in opposition to “religious”; rather, informed by the path-breaking inquiries of the two scholars whose work I want to engage here, the anthropologist Talal Asad and the political theorist William Connolly, I understand the secular as a concept that articulates a constellation of institutions, ideas, and affective orientations that constitute an important dimension of what we call modernity and its defining forms of knowledge and practice—both religious and non-religious. The secular is, in Asad’s words, “conceptually prior to the political doctrine of secularism,” and it is therefore part of the background presupposed by our routine ways of distinguishing secular from religious in law, politics, ethics, and aesthetics.
But let me return to the reflection I had going. I had suggested a little unease with the idea of sending a student off to the university classroom as a site in which to study the formation of the embodied capacities of secular subjects. What about the psychoanalyst’s couch? Or the gym at the YMCA? Or a training seminar for advertising executives? Clearly some of the habits and attitudes honed within such sites of modern self-fashioning must qualify as “secular.” But again the question is begged: what are we implying—conceptually, historically, institutionally—when we designate such affects and attitudes (I am using a copious vocabulary of embodiment) as secular, as opposed to, say, “modern, or “liberal,” perhaps”? I don’t think an answer to this question is readily forthcoming, and the problem is not simply one of an adequate definition.
One reason for our hesitation and uncertainty around this question undoubtedly owes to the difficulty of establishing an analytical distance from what is clearly a foundational dimension of modern life. The secular is the water we swim in. It is for this reason that Talal Asad, in the “Introduction” to his Formations of the Secular, cautions us against approaching it directly, suggesting instead that “it is best pursued through its shadows.” In this regard, my starting question—What is a secular body?—is blindingly direct, and therefore a rather blunt analytical instrument. That said, I still think it may have its use, less in terms of the answers we are able to give to it than by the kinds of resistance we encounter when we try. That is, to follow where this question runs aground, where it is deflected, postponed, perhaps where it becomes obtuse, uninteresting, may help us to elucidate some of the contours of the concept we are concerned with. Is it the wrong question to ask? Does it force us to rethink our models of embodiment, habitus, sensibility? An answer to these questions could be very useful for getting a better grasp of the secular.
I have chosen to focus on the works of Talal Asad and Bill Connolly because of the impact these works have had on how we have come to pose questions about the secular and secularism. Moreover, within the respective analytical frameworks they have developed, they have strongly foregrounded issues of embodiment—Asad privileging notions of sensibility and attitude, Connolly building a rich and heterogeneous philosophical vocabulary of the passions from such sources as Spinoza, Nietzsche, and Deleuze, among others. In what follows, I want to explore the question I raised above by means of the analyses put forward by these scholars concerning the embodied character of the secular. In this regard, my goal here is very modest. I ask: What kind of answers do we find in the work of these two scholars to the question, “What is a secular body”? And what might these answers—or refusals to answer—tell us about the practical and conceptual contours of the secular and secularism?
II
Let me start by noting that, while the secular body may remain something of an enigma, we do know quite a lot about the techniques that different religious traditions have developed in order to hone a pious sensorium, i.e., the embodied aptitudes and affects necessary for the achievement of a virtuous life as defined by those traditions. One of the richest and most influential examples of such scholarship is Asad’s own pioneering work on techniques of the body practiced by medieval Christian monks. Extending insights from Marcel Mauss’s writings on body techniques and Foucault’s inquiries into Greek and Christian arts of self-cultivation, Asad examined a variety of disciplinary exercises and techniques of self-cultivation (in short, ritual practices) by which medieval Christians sought to reshape their wills, desires, and emotions in accord with authoritative standards of virtue. I mention this work here because it provides an extremely useful model for thinking about the interrelation of knowledge, practice, and embodiment within a tradition, directing us to forms of collective and individual discipline and to the concepts of self and body that inform them. It is interesting, therefore to note at the outset that, despite an emphasis on embodied modes of appraisal in both Asad’s Formations and Connolly’s Why I am not a Secularist, descriptions of self-cultivation or practices of self-discipline are largely (though not entirely, as I note below) absent from both texts. That is, we find very little in these works in regard, not only to how the sensibilities and visceral modes of judgment of secular subjects are cultivated, but to how they give shape to and find expression in a secular life? Admittedly, a cautious approach to this issue is entirely warranted in light of how new and unfamiliar the secular is as a research problem. Nonetheless, I want to look at certain points in these texts where this question is most directly addressed. One word of warning: the few comments I will make on Asad’s and Connolly’s writings barely scratch the surface of these immensely rich books.
Why I am not a Secularist combines an analysis of secular discourses on ethics, politics, and language with an attempt to show how an engagement with traditions that incorporate an appreciation for affective and visceral registers of existence can be used to generate resources for a productive and necessary revision of secular thinking. Not surprisingly, most of Connolly’s exploration of the embodied character of political judgment is focused on thinkers who stand at some remove from the dominant currents of secular thought, while his treatment of secular arguments tends overall to emphasize the dangers and limitations of their failing to thematize the visceral register. There are, however, certain points in his discussion where the question of a secular bodily ethics comes up. Informed in part by Asad’s account of monastic disciplinary techniques, Connolly writes: “it may be important to understand how representational discourse itself, including the public expression and defense of fundamental beliefs, affects and is affected by the visceral register of intersubjectivity. Public discourses do operate within dense linguistic fields that specify how beliefs are to be articulated and tested and how ethical claims are to be redeemed. But repetitions and defenses of these articulations also write scripts upon prerepresentational sites of appraisal.” The practice of articulating and defending secular political claims, he suggests here, serves to mold and deepen the affective attachments that passionally bind one to the secular form of life those claims uphold. This is one of the few locations where Connolly connects his conceptual analysis of the secular with a kind of institutional practice, albeit a highly discourse-centered one. The question to ask, it seems to me, is: Why, in a book so centered around the task of rethinking secular politics, is there so little attention to the affective attachments that secure the authority of secular political judgments? I will come back to this later.
Perhaps the most visceral element of the secular discourses identified by Connolly is their rejection of the visceral dimension itself. Kantian and neo-Kantian political philosophies devalue forms of life that give priority to their own sensory dimensions, a standpoint that secures the possibility of regulating the place of religion in public life insomuch as religion is understood to privilege this passional, sensual register. Indeed, for Connolly the value of religious traditions for political thought today lies precisely in the resources such traditions offer for thinking about the contribution of affective experience to shaping our practices of political judgment and reason. Secularism suffers, in his view, from its failure to thematize the place of what he calls the infrasensible register—affects and dispositions operating below the threshold of consciousness—within its own style of reasoning.
Kant’s marginalization of Christian theology in favor of a “rational religion” grounded in moral reasoning is a key moment, in Connolly’s account, in the philosophical development of this moral repulsion for the visceral. As he notes, Kant “degrades ritual and arts of the self without eliminating them altogether, for these arts work on the ‘sensibility’ rather than drawing moral obligation from the supersensible realm as practical reason does. The point is to deploy them just enough to render crude sensibilities better equipped to accept the moral law drawn from practical reason. Secularists later carry this Kantian project of diminishment a step or two further.”
I want to pause on this point to ask where it might lead us in thinking about a secular sensorium, or about the sensibilities that give shape to a secular life. Kant’s treatment of the question of sensibility is guided and limited by his primary aim of securing the purity of the moral will, its protection from what are seen to be the contaminating effects of sensible desire. This is achieved through his positing of a two-world metaphysic that ensures the autonomy of the moral will by assigning it to the domain of the supersensible while circumscribing the role of the passions and habits to the sphere of sensible life. Honed sensibilities and practices of self-cultivation do have a positive function in disciplining the cruder drives within the self, but they never directly contribute to moral reasoning. As Kant notes, in a comment cited by Connolly: “Ethical gymnastics, therefore, consists only in combating natural impulses sufficiently to be able to master them when a situation comes up in which they threaten morality; hence it makes one valiant and cheerful in the consciousness of one’s restored freedom.”
One place where we do find in Kant a discussion of sensibilities, and hence a text that might point us toward a conception of a secular sensorium, is in his Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. While the question of sensibilities is discussed in many parts of that text, here I will simply mention one particular, and highly ritualistic, moment, the dinner party scene, in which Kant lays out a set of guidelines for the dinner host to follow in order to engender the sort of civilized sociability that befits Kantian rational beings: topics that may engender more violent passions among the guests must be avoided at all costs (as must music!); the thread of a conversation must not be interrupted until it has reached its natural conclusion; “deadly silence” must be strictly avoided. Overall, the goal is to maintain a conversational tone that befits a “well-bred, partly sensuous and partly ethicointellectual, human being,” so as to harmonize the inclination to good living with the inclination to virtue and the moral law such that the former does not hinder the latter.
Following Connolly, I would read Kant’s dinner party rules as a pedagogical device geared to disciplining the emotions and attitudes of a secular subject. Why secular (again, as opposed to, say, modern)? If I understand Connolly correctly, it is because the style of restrained emotional expression that Kant encourages provides a normative image of public reason against which the more passional forms of sociability and knowledge associated with religious sects are found to be inadequate, and thus subject to regulation in accord with the doctrine of political secularism. We might say, the secular subject—the Kantian dinner host—is one whose speech and comportment incorporates a recognition of the distinctions authorized by the twin categories of religious and secular. Put differently, a secular person is someone whose affective-gestural repertoires express a negative relation to forms of embodiment historically associated with (but not limited to) theistic religion.
I am trying here to delineate a path that Connolly’s work opens up for asking about what I first called the secular body. While the path seemed clear at the outset, it now appears far less so, for the following reason. From the sixteenth to the eighteenth century, a variety of social transformations took place that are key to our understanding of the emergence of the modern subject, among them, the desensualization of knowledge as described by Ong, the stilling of passionate expression within courtly society that Elias has examined, and, more generally, the increasing internalization of psychic and emotional life within bourgeois society, the transfer of vast realms of experience from the surface of public life into the invisible depths of the lonely individual. These conceptual and social transformations, to which Kant contributed, were not the result of a single overarching process, but were propelled by different, if sometimes interlinking, historical trajectories, circumstances, and problems. In light of this, and recognizing the indebtedness of Kant’s own viewpoints on reason and the senses to these prior developments, should we say that these transformations are part of the genealogy of the secular? To say so, it seems, would entail losing a great deal of the specificity and historical locatedness of that term. So, what aspects of the modern soul are properly secular, and to which history of the body should they be ascribed?
Let me see if I can develop this line of inquiry further by drawing on some of the arguments put forward by Talal Asad in Formations of the Secular. Let me start by saying a little about what I take Asad to mean be the “the secular.” In his chapter on an “Anthropology of Secularism,” which I will focus on here, he states: “I take the secular to be a concept that brings together certain behaviors, knowledges, and sensibilities in modern life.” To explore these dimensions of the secular, he examines shifts in the grammar of a number of concepts—myth, the sacred, pain, the human—concepts that articulate practices we have come to identify as secular. The practices that he takes as secular, in other words, are so, not simply because they are non-religious, but because they have been discursively identified and valorized through the discourse of secularism (as distinct from the political doctrine). For Asad, a practice is not secular because it stands in a particular relation to the political doctrine of secularism. Rather, the historical discourse of the secular, as predicated on the opposition religious/secular, is integral to the grammar of the concepts he examines.
Let me draw on two examples from this first chapter in order to pursue the question of secular embodiment. In one section, Asad explores how shifts in the grammar of the concept of myth contributed to the development of the secular tradition of Romantic poetry. For poets such as Blake and Coleridge, the “mythic method,” as Asad refers to it, provided a secular means by which spiritual truths could be accessed and given expression. Instead of the virtue of faith, such poetic geniuses needed only to tune into their deep inner feelings and express these sincerely. Elaborating on these Romantic notions, Asad notes, “This may help to explain the prevalence among Victorian unbelievers of what Stefan Collini calls ‘a rhetoric of sincerity.’ For not only was the idea of being true to oneself conceived of as a moral duty, it also presupposed the existence of a secular self whose sovereignty had to be demonstrated through acts of sincerity. The self’s secularity consisted in the fact that it was the precondition of transcendent (poetic or religious) experience and not its product.” I call attention to this section because it provides an example of what might be called a practice of secular self-fashioning: the honing of a rhetoric of sincerity as necessary to the cultivation of the secular subject. Moreover, there are interesting parallels to be drawn between the romantic emphasis on sincerity and the Protestant concern for the sincerity of speech within ritual professions of faith. But why does Asad not develop this line of inquiry, especially in light of how important such question were within his work on medieval monasticism? Why, I ask, are there so few descriptions of practices in a book explicitly focused on the sensory and embodied dimensions of the secular?
A number of the chapters in Formations explore different aspects of the changing grammar of pain. One element of this change concerns a turning away from a Christian discourse on sin and punishment in ministering to pain and the development, in contrast, of a scientific vocabulary and experimental methods for addressing pain. “In this example,” Asad writes, referring to Rosalind Rey’s discussion of pain during the Enlightenment, “the secularization of pain signals not merely the abandonment of a transcendental language (“religious obsessions”) but the shift to a new preoccupation—from the personal attempt at consoling and curing (that is, inhabiting a social relationship) to a distanced attempt at investigating the functions and sensations of the living body.” As Asad emphasizes, the new practices surrounding pain and suffering are not adequately grasped in terms of the notion of “disenchantment”—as a secularist narrative asserts—“when what is at stake are different patterns of sensibility about pain, and different ways of objectifying it.” Asad pursues this inquiry into the secularization of pain and the shifting attitudes, sensibilities, and knowledges that have propelled it from a variety of different angles, as it bears, for example, on the practice of human rights, on the conduct of war, on childbirth, on sadomasochism. Given my limited space here, let me stay with his discussion of the emergence of an experimental science of pain. We recognize in Asad’s account of the secularization of pain, with its new sensibilities, styles of objectification, mechanistic concepts of the body and its processes, the basis for contemporary biomedical practice. As we know, biomedical models and forms of reasoning play an immense and growing role in modern society, in terms of both the institutions that regulate the many facets of our lives that fall under the rubric of “health” as well as concepts and practices through which we understand and respond to many dimensions of our experience. In this light, would it be correct to state that the regime of knowledge and power that we call “biomedical” plays a significant role in constituting the secular, and that the disciplinary exercises and institutions put into play by this regime shape us—our attitudes, our visceral reasoning, our patterned hierarchies of the senses—as secular people? In putting forward this suggestion, I am undoubtedly pushing Asad’s cautious and careful inquiry well beyond the kinds of claim he would embrace—but I am interested in trying to ascertain why such an expansion of what we refer to as “secular” strikes us as unjustified or wrong (if indeed it does).
One reason for resisting the equation of biomedicine with the secular would be that we lose a grasp of what is unique to secularity, that the genealogy of the secular becomes fused with and indistinguishable from the genealogy of the modern. We lose an understanding of the way the practice of distinguishing religious from secular gives impetus to the set of shifts that constitute the secular—and hence we lose a sense of precisely what is secular about our contemporary biomedical practices. In other words, the secular dimension of them, the way that they embed a form of reasoning that has its historical basis in the production and mobilization of the religious/secular opposition escapes us. From this perspective, we are right to call our regime of health “secular” but we are not in a position to understand what this entails, lacking as we do, an adequate analysis of how we got here.
In this light, my original question—Is there a secular body?—appears not wrong but premature. We could now understand what I have traced as a certain hesitation and reluctance to give flesh to a secular subject within Asad’s and Connolly’s writing as being founded in a recognition of the danger entailed in posing this question too quickly.
My sense in reading these two subtle inquiries into the secular, however, is that the authors’ reticence to speak about the embodied capacities and dispositions of a secular subject is not just the result of scholarly prudence, but that it reflects, rather, something about the concept of the secular. What we have seen is that, each time we attempt to characterize a secular subject in terms of a determinant set of embodied dispositions, we lose a sense of what “secular” refers to. Note as well that, while the statement, “He lives a very religious life” gives us some sense of the shape of a life, “He lives a very secular life” tells us almost nothing (except, negatively, that the person does not engage in practices of worship). In contrast, when we speak about secular history, or secular time, or secular literature, or even a secular discourse on pain, we seem to know our way about—in a Wittgensteinian sense of having a feel for the use of our term within certain language games.
To this point, I have attempted to trace out some of the various ways that our attempts to speak about, or theorize, a secular body encounter resistance. What might this resistance tell us about our category of the secular? In the space that remains, I want to explore one possible direction toward an answer to this question.
In both Asad’s and Connolly’s writings, the secular identity of a practice is not simply due to its philosophical foundations—its grounding in a rationalist, empiricist, or materialist perspective, for example. Rather, the practices they explore under the rubric of the secular are those that have emerged through a process of differentiation structured by the binaries of religion/secular, belief/knowledge, sacred/profane, and so on. This is not simply to say that the categories of religious and secular are historically entwined, or that they are reciprocally defining (like man and woman, for example), but that the secular marks a relational dynamic more than an identity. We might restate this argument to say that, at least in many cases, a practice or a sensibility that we designate “secular” is one that depends upon, one that cannot be abstracted from, the secularist narrative of the progressive replacement of religious error by secular reason—what Asad calls the “triumphalist narrative of secularism.” Or, again, in a slightly different formulation, a secular sensibility is one considered from the standpoint of its contribution to that progressivist narrative.
Let me try to clarify this point through an example. Take the tradition of Romantic poetry discussed by Asad. Asad’s account of the emergence of this tradition focuses on a number of early nineteenth-century developments in aesthetic, religious, and scientific practice, including the development of a secular discourse on the meaning of inspiration, and new uses of the idea of myth within both historical and fictional genres of writing. Why is the history of Romantic poetry a starting point for Asad in his attempt to develop an anthropology of the secular? On one hand, this tradition allows Asad to challenge accounts of a necessary or natural superseding of the religious by the secular, by exploring some of the historical contingencies that together enabled a new, so-called secular practice to emerge. More importantly, it is a tradition that owes its aesthetic values to a particular authorizing narrative, one highlighting the movement from religious to secular (from the prophet to the poet; from divine inspiration to creative genius). The sensibilities that the romantic poet’s work gave expression to, and which shaped his audience’s cultivated response, I want to suggest, depended on the rhetoric of secularization (the forward movement from error to truth) as a condition of their exercise. (It is worth noting here that many modern practices, be they aesthetic or social or political, are not subject to the play of the secular/religious opposition, and are not validated by reference to this binarism.)
How does the account of the secular I am suggesting here bear on the problem of the secular sensorium, or what I called the secular body? Let me try to answer this by reference to one particular tradition for thinking embodiment, that afforded by the Aristotelian notions of habitus and virtue. In my earlier book, The Ethical Soundscape, I explored how this tradition had contributed to shaping an Islamic practice of listening to sermons in contemporary Egypt, both in the ritual context of Friday worship and outside the mosque through the audition of cassette recorded sermons. As I described in that book, many people listen to sermons as a means of ethical self-improvement, a way to reinforce and deepen not only their knowledge of Islamic doctrines but also the ethical emotions and attitudes they understand as enabling correct styles of speech, comportment, and moral judgment. Coupled with the proliferation of new listening practices among ordinary Egyptians, sermon tapes provided one of the means by which Islamic ethical traditions were recalibrated to a new political and technological order, to its rhythms, noise, its forms of pleasure and boredom, but also to its political incitements, its call to citizenly participation. In contrast to a space for the formation of political opinion through intersubjective reason, the discursive arena wherein cassette sermons circulate, I argued, is geared to the deployment of the disciplining power of ethical speech, a goal, however, that takes public deliberation as one of its modalities. Within this context, public speech results not in policy, but in pious dispositions, the embodied sensibilities and modes of expression understood to facilitate the development and practice of Islamic virtues and, therefore, of Islamic ethical comportment. The cassette-listeners I worked with sought to forge a habitus—in their terms, such virtues of modesty, humility, and fear of God—that would allow them to achieve excellence in the practices that they saw as essential to Islamic traditions of ethical reasoning, and thus to the revitalization and maintenance of an Islamic society.
Romantic poets, of course, also sought to hone skills that would allow them to achieve excellence in the aesthetic practices they undertook. What distinguishes these two contexts? Sermon listening takes place in and contributes to a tradition of moral reasoning, with its internal notions of the good and a changing repertoire of practices by which the good is to be achieved. The honed sensibilities of the Romantic poet, on the other hand, contribute to the project of the secular only insomuch as they are grasped as part of the movement of negation and overcoming by which the secular emerges from the religious. We might say that the poetic sensibilities themselves are not secular (nor religious, for that matter), but they can be encompassed and appropriated within the narrative of the secular emancipation from religion. They are sensibilities that fit into the game of secularism.
III
The secularist movement as it developed in the mid-nineteenth century encompassed both positive and negative impulses. Its founders, most importantly Robert Owen and G. J. Holyoake, sought, on the positive side, to uncover a new system of moral truth, founded on rationalist, utilitarian, and materialist principles. As Holyoake wrote in 1853: “Secularism is the province of the real, the known, the useful, and the affirmative. It is the practical side of skepticism.” Its negative side lay in its relentless attack on what early secularists called the “speculative error” of religion. The career of our concept of the secular has been shaped by this double vocation, one in which the positive attempt to ground an ethical and epistemological foundation remains dependent on a negative gesture whereby the forms of knowledge and practice posited as religious are continuously overcome. While these twin movements have played an immense role in shaping what we recognize and valorize as the secular-modern, they also account for a kind of instability at the heart of the secular, one evident in the difficulties we encounter when asking about the secular body.
IV
Let me conclude these rather tentative and exploratory reflections by suggesting why such an inquiry is important, particularly for scholars of Islam. It has become increasingly apparent in recent years that any study of contemporary religious traditions necessitates some engagement with religion’s dialectical partner, the secular, understood as a key dimension of the moral, social, and political transformations that have shaped global modernity. Yet, while we have a good understanding of how the doctrine of political secularism—the state-imposed legal separation of religion and politics—has impacted the conceptual and practical development of religious life in many contexts, including Islamic ones, such as in Turkey, Egypt, or Indonesia, we have little sense of the social ontology of the secular, and the kinds of practices, sensibilities, and knowledges that it opens up. Moreover, and as I hope I have made clear, to assimilate the secular to the modern, as has often been the scholarly approach, tells us very little about a key constitutive dimension of modernity.
A secular body has been characterised as a body purely designed for carrying around a head. There is an orientation to the space between the eye-brows and so on.
There probably isn’t one secular body just as there isn’t one religious body (the idealised Greek figure is quite different to the Indian or the Arabic), nor one religious philosophy.
There are various systems of bodywork that can help with the detail of the description(s).
Thanks very much for the thought-provoking post. My concern, though related, is a bit different: how to make sense of an (apparently) complex phenomenon or (perhaps) an oxymoron such as “secular Muslim”. Am not referring to a hypothetical situation. It is based on my ethnographic fieldwork among “secular Muslims” in India. The “secular” in this context may be interpreted in the word’s peculiar Indian sense of opposition to politicised religion (communalism) or “tolerance” of other religions (some kind of a recipe for peaceful coexistence, in other words). But that does not address the issue entirely.
The “secular Muslims” are at the margins of the Islamic community in India because they deny the scriptural status of hadith and claim that the Qur’an is the sole scripture of Islam. They interpret the Qur’an mostly metaphorically—inter alia, they believe that since all “religions” are true and equal before Allah one need not be a Muslim (as distinct from a Christian, Jew, Hindu etc.) to attain heaven. In other words, they deny the uniqueness of Islam as a “religion”. A “Muslim” (one who has submitted to God, literally understood) is anybody who believes in the one God (no matter how you name Him—Allah, YHWH, Ishwar) and after-life (where one will be rewarded or punished for what one did on earth), and does good works (fulfill one’s duties, help the needy etc.). Freedom from “religion” is what is necessary for this. And, according to them, the qur’anic word “deen” (usually translated as religion) means only “opinion.” Further, this is not merely a matter of holding the correct belief. An active cultivation of the self (in terms of developing certain dispositions, attitudes, sensibilities etc.) is necessary to become a “secular Muslim”. For instance, “secular Muslims” claim that “salat” means commitment and not the obligatory daily prayers (as is the generally acknowledged interpretation among Muslims). One need not pray at all, but be committed to whatever you do in one’s daily life (job, responsibilities towards one’s family, society, country etc.). Being a patriotic Indian and treating the country’s Constitution as sacrosanct can be “salat”, the argument goes. Similarly, the first pillar of Islam is getting educated and gaining knowledge (not just religious, but all kinds, especially the natural sciences) and not the “shahada” (the profession of faith, which is rarely mentioned by “secular Muslims”). In several ways they create a counter-public within Islam.
It is interesting to note how the “secular Muslim’s” faith views “Islam” as the “religion of the end of religion.” Being a “secular Muslim” is about the end of “Islam” as we know it. “Emancipation from religion” is a precondition to becoming “Muslim.” It hinges on a radical reinterpretation of almost all its core concepts. True, theologically speaking, it may be possible to refute it and deny them the status of “Muslims” (as most other Indian Muslim scholars do). But that is not the job of a social scientist. How do we understand the “secular Muslim” body? How does a seemingly “secular” commitment (salat) as doing one’s job properly and sincerely become part of an Islamic sensibility, particularly when it is totally divorced from any rituals whatsoever? They endorse the “tawhid” (belief in the one and only Allah) and accept the finality of Mohammed’s Prophethood. That much is in line with mainstream Islam. So, perhaps even theologically, one cannot argue that they are not Muslims. But, when it comes to several other tenets of the faith, they differ radically from other Muslims. So where does the “secular” end and the “religious” begin in the case of a “secular Muslim”? Will the “dialectical” relation between the categories of the “secular” and the “religious” help in understanding them? Or should one go beyond them?
Thanks for a provocative and instructive piece. I don’t understand, however, how we can think about the secular body without taking psychoanalysis into account. Kant’s dinner party is a fine example of the “civilizing process” (and its secular ramifications), but how can we think ‘the body’ without sex, without sexual difference, without drives and desires? It seems to me that Freud is the theorist we need to engage with here, not for definitive answers, but for one way of elucidating the problem in all its complexity.
There is one stream in this extremely informative discussion that I think is worth pulling out and making more explicit. At the beginning you mention your unease about sending students to certain spaces in order to try to understand some of the elements of what make up the secular body, and towards the end you mention the research of your earlier book (which was foundational for me as I began to explore these issues). In between, we come to understand some of what is so insightful about Connolly’s and Asad’s work, yet what binds together your prior work and (I am assuming) your pedagogy is a properly ethnographic dimension that only pokes its head up in brief moments throughout this post.
And yet it is the ethnographic that so powerfully explains why the critical evaluation of secularism and its sensory, affective, dispositional, cultivational, corporeal, and practice-oriented dimensions is so important for scholars of Islam. The historical tradition assumed by the critical study of secularism, which draws in Holyoake, Owen, Kant’s dinner party, the philosophers discussed in Why I am Not a Secularist, and the romantic poets in Asad’s analysis, as well as historical religious subjects like Asad’s medieval monks, are not simply absent in Islamic contexts, but their alternative genealogy cannot fully help us capture the complexity of the political and social dynamics of places like Egypt, Indonesia, and Turkey, where secular assumptions about what kind of body is rational, modern, and liberal meet, condense with, suture to, fight against, and weave together with “religious” or Islamic modes of action and bodily practices. Perhaps the Islamic world is so interesting for this work because, there, “the secular marks a relational dynamic more than an identity” in a way that is loudly and constantly contested as also a geographic relational dynamic. In America, the secular and religious traditions are widely considered both “local” in some sense, while in Egypt, at the very least, the question of the “social ontology” of the secular is connected to global modernity and its “Western” (too simplistic, I know) assumptions.
Certainly, as you point out, it is difficult to study the “secular” body as opposed to the “liberal” or “modern” because A) Secularism as a doctrine does not explicitly engage in the kinds of bodily ritual worship that mark religious doctrines and B) much of what we consider the “secular” comes into being just as it becomes inseparable from its rejection of, and hence recognition of, the “religious.” It is relational by nature. Thus, how do we profess to understand it outside of those ethnographic spaces, especially but not only Islamic (the American public space of action works as well), in which it is at its most relational, that is to say, its most agonistic, in which it is forced to exist precisely because it exists in such tension with what it defines as “religious”?
The production and scholarly consumption of texts cannot approach the issue of the secular body head on because a large dimension of the secular body, assuming the agonistic nature of the secular, is bound up with affective states like disgust and anger (as Connolly explores in American contexts). Yet the interpretation of the affective can only do so much when bound to texts and not, at the very least, engaging ethnographic instances like those you have approached in Egypt. There is work to be done on both ends as we struggle to conceptualize the secular body, and I just don’t want the ethnographic, controversial and unhip as it often is, to get lost. It seems to be, at this juncture, an underexplored route to really talk about affect, and hence the secular body.
Thank you for getting me thinking more deeply about this.
Is there a point made when someone says there is no such thing as Secularism (capital S)? Does not secular simply imply a neutral political space through which a morally divided polity can attempt to form a democratic majority? The sphere of nature and of the forum are bounded and regarded first politically by sectarian interests and only regarded as neutral “secular” space when the interests of public peace and democracy override personal interest as moral imperatives. Is not a representative government first formed in such a space in order to stabilize the balance of secular democracy and sectarian majorities?
To claim “the secular” then, is like hijacking “natural law” to validate one’s views. While the scientific method is similar in spirit, it does not provide political authority it only supports personal conviction in favor of democracy and disinterested experimentation. To embody it, therefore, is to rob it of that open, transcendent aspect that defines and validates it politically. If the method is overused and turned oppressive, it is the failure of the dominant personal or sectarian moral narratives and conventions as always in terms of how *they* relate to the secular precedents of their society. Secular Humanism would then be much more of a contradiction in terms than Secular Islam because it attempts to make absolute the method itself rather than simply moderating the actual human interests democracy and debate are there to preserve. When any interest lays claim to the secular they invite the radicalization of their opponents.
Thanks for an interesting post. I was wondering if it would help to look at the problem of the secular body, taking a step backward.
What if we were to ask, Why do we want an answer to the question “is there a secular body?” I guess the response will be to say, we want it so that we can understand the conditions of persuasion of secularism. That is, we can know how secularism as a concept lives on in our minds, without our explanations necessarily taking recourse to the doctrinal correctness or persuasion of secularism. However, is it at all possible in this instance?
Do the believer’s attitudes have a bearing on the truth of religion? The answer is, yes. They do, because it is through these attitudes that the truth of religion is mediated to the believer. Now if we take another example, that of the natural sciences: do a scientist’s attitudes, beliefs and sensibilities have any bearing on the truth of the scientific theory? The answer is, no. Not because scientific truths are objective but because the truth claims of the natural sciences do not require any non-deductive component to be true. (This does not, however, mean that natural science does not induce its own set of attitudes and affects in its practitioners. It only means that the affects and attitudes in this case are contingent, derivative and therefore trivial, and do not have any significant cognitive relationship to the beliefs harbored by the scientist in question).
Is it possible that secularism, in so far as it is not seen as a mode of understanding or being in the world, but is seen as a theory about the world, also renders the affects and attitudes it begets as contingent, derivative and therefore semantically thin?
One might ask, doesn’t doctrinal religion also assume that it is a theory about the world? Yes. But insofar as religion includes the development of a repertoire of actions and orientations to the world (as evidenced through a rich array of action-orienting concepts like piety, chastity, modesty, kindness and so on), we can say that the actions and affects within the religious sphere were in a genuine dialectic with beliefs. However, this may not be true in the secular world (as evidenced by our secular concepts, which have no such capacity: rights, freedom, equality, privacy and so on). And in the natural sciences it is impossible to derive even a single action-orienting concept from the practice of science (avoiding the use of plastic to save the environment is precisely not affect and action in a genuine dialectic with belief. That is, put simply, avoiding the use of plastic does not help you know anything more about the environment than you already did).
Thanks for insightful post. There are many aspects which can simply be appreciated and I am in agreement with most of them. But there is one particular aspect where I feel that something has been assumed rather less critically. It pertains to the categorical difference, as asserted by the blogger, of sense generation when we are informed that someone is living a religious life and another is living a secular life. The eminent blogger has specifically mentioned that living a religious life gives us some sense of living life religiously as if there were some particular ways of religious life. But as far as a life lived secularly is concerned, we do not get any sense of living it secularly because of the reason that there is no specific way to live life secularly.
The blogger is right that there is some sense created when we think that someone lives a religious life. But the issue is that this sense is not appreciated by everybody similarly. One may take it in one way and the other may take it in entirely different way. So the generated sense is not the same; it is diversified and shaped by our own experiences of observing people living religious lives. Similarly, if we view the secular life from perspectives of those who assert that they live secular lives and those who endeavor to portray what is truly secular way of life we will also have some sense generated by the information of living life secularly. In this way if we approach secular from individual perspectives of people then it may also generate some sense similar to the sense generated by the religious life even if this sense is not equal to the sense generated by the religious life. Therefore, the contested assertion of the blogger, that some sense is generated with religious life but not with secular life, is more rhetorical than real and the purpose appears to emphasis his main point that there is no secular body.